The Belmont Report principle of beneficence requires that

You are here

The Belmont Report states that “persons are treated in an ethical manner not only by respecting their decisions and protecting them from harm, but also by making efforts to secure their well-being.” Securing a research subject’s well-being falls under the principle of beneficence. Beneficence, as described in the Belmont Report, obligates the investigator to follow two general rules. The first is to “do no harm,” and the second is to “maximize possible benefits and minimize possible harms.” With respect to the first general rule of beneficence, the authors of the Belmont Report did not intend for investigators to reach the standard of “above all do no harm” (primum non nocere), which is commonly said to be the first principle of medical ethics. Rather, the Commission intended to forbid the deliberate injury of a human subject for the purpose of developing generalizable new knowledge, no matter how important that knowledge might be. They endorsed the acceptability of exposing an individual subject to a possibility (or statistical probability) of injury as long as an IRB determined that this was justified in light of the probability and magnitude of the sought-for benefits. Benefits may accrue to individual subjects or, through the development of generalized knowledge, to society, perhaps in the form of better health care. Risks, however, are borne by individual subjects. The risks and benefits of research are not always known, and investigators, along with the IRBs that approve their protocols, must decide with imperfect knowledge when it is justifiable to seek certain benefits despite the risks involved, and when the benefits should be foregone because of the risks.

The second general rule of beneficence obligates investigators to design their protocols so as to maximize the probability and magnitude of benefits to individual research subjects as well as to society. It further requires investigators to minimize the probability and magnitude of injury to individual research subjects. It is during the process of informed consent that the risks of participation in research are disclosed and that a promise to pursue the individual or collective benefits is made with each potential subject.

Some authors have argued that the two general rules described above are actually two fundamental ethical principles, beneficence (do good) and nonmaleficence (do no harm). However, others feel beneficence should be viewed as a single principle, because in a research context, it is necessary to consider harms and benefits in relation to each other.

Beneficence – Philosophical Foundation

The authors of the Belmont Report drew upon medical tradition when considering the ethical principle of beneficence. It is commonly said that the first principle of medical ethics is “do no harm.” This principle can trace its origin back over 2,500 years to Hippocrates. However, the National Commission recognized that “even avoiding harm requires learning what is harmful; and, in the process of obtaining this information, persons may be exposed to the risk of harm. Further, the Hippocratic Oath requires physicians to benefit their patients ‘according to their best judgment.’ Learning what will in fact benefit may require exposing persons to risk.” Determining when the pursuit of certain benefits is justified despite the risks is the difficult question faced daily by investigators and IRBs.

Although beneficence is generally viewed as acts of kindness and charity which individuals are not obligated to pursue or bestow upon others, the National Commission viewed beneficence (to do or promote good) as a strict obligation or duty in the research context, because investigators consent or pledge to be bound by it. Investigators pledge to promote good, by creating new knowledge or providing some benefit to subjects, when they accept public support for their work. In addition, during the process of informed consent, investigators pledge to pursue the benefits with potential subjects. It would be unethical to put human beings at risk without the prospect of creating beneficial new knowledge or promoting the social good. In each case, the foundation of the obligation is like the obligation to keep promises.

An investigator’s ethical obligation to treat subjects with beneficence is primarily carried out during the process of assessing and balancing the risks and benefits faced by subjects (See Module 3). However, ethical norms derived from this principle are discussed in each of the modules. 

The Belmont Report principle of beneficence requires that
 Print

Purpose and Applicability

All UW human subjects research is guided by the statement of ethical principles called the Belmont Report. This guidance is intended to present human subjects regulatory concepts within the context of the Belmont Ethical Principles.

Context

In an attempt to strengthen human research protections, the National Research Act was passed in 1974. As part of this Act, the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research was created and tasked with developing a code of human subjects research ethics. The Commission published the Belmont Report in 1976 which identified the following basic ethical principles:

  1. Respect for Persons expresses the ethical convictions that the autonomy of individuals should be respected and that persons with diminished autonomy are entitled to equal protection.
  2. Beneficence describes an obligation to protect subjects from harm by maximizing possible benefits and minimizing possible harms.
  3. Justice promotes equitable representation in research in terms of fairly distributing the risks and benefits of research.

The Belmont Ethical Principles provided the foundation for the Common Rule (45 CFR 46) human subjects research regulations. This guidance page describes regulatory concepts, such as consent, within the context of these ethical principles. Additional content will be added over time.

The requirements for Respect for Persons are satisfied when subjects are provided with a meaningful consent process in which they are provided with all relevant information about a study that a reasonable person would need and that they fully comprehend the information they are provided. This helps to ensure that they are able to make a voluntary decision about whether or not to participate.

The requirements for Beneficence are met when the anticipated risks and benefits of research are disclosed to prospective subjects as part of the consent process and in the consent form (if there is a form).

The principle of Justice is most relevant to consent in the context of equitable selection of subjects. It is important to consider whether the subject populations(s) who bear the risks of research might also stand to benefit from it and, conversely, whether those populations most likely to benefit from the research are also being asked to share in the risks.

The Belmont Principles can conflict with each other with respect to research consent. Considerations of Beneficence must be balanced against an obligation to allow for subject autonomy when subjects have consent capacity (Respect for Persons) and promoting equitable representation in research (Justice). The IRB and researchers will need to consider the particulars of each study and subject population to identify the appropriate balance between the principles.

Example: Children participating in research do not provide consent on their own behalf. Rather, a parent or guardian provides their permission and the child, when they have the capacity, provides assent. The Belmont Principles may conflict with each other when the child does not want to enroll in the study but their parent/guardian wants them to be enrolled.

In general, a child’s dissent should be respected (Respect for Persons) and every effort should be made to come to a consensus between the child and their parent/guardian. However, there are some circumstances involving children where the regulations favor Beneficence and Justice over Respect for Persons:

  • When the research is greater than minimal risk and there is a potential for direct benefit to the child, the IRB may allow the wishes of a single parent/guardian to override the wishes of the child in order to obtain the benefit (Beneficence).
  • The IRB may approve greater than minimal risk research where the only likely benefit is the knowledge to be gained for other children with the disorder or condition being treated (Justice). However, the IRB will generally require two-parent permission in these cases as an additional safeguard that the risks are reasonable given the anticipated benefits (Beneficence).

GUIDANCE Consent

Regulatory References

  • 45 CFR 46
  • The Belmont Report: Ethical Principles and Guidelines for the Protection of Human Subjects of Research. The National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research, April 18, 1979

Version Information

Open the accordion below for version changes to this guidance.

Version NumberPosted DateImplementation DateChange Notes
1.00 10.08.2021 10.08.2021 Newly posted guidance.

Key words: Ethical principles

What are the 3 principles of the Belmont Report quizlet?

The three principles discussed in the Belmont Report are Respect for Persons, Beneficence, Justice.

What are the 3 basic principles of the Belmont Report?

The Belmont Report Three basic principles, among those generally accepted in our cultural tradition, are particularly relevant to the ethics of research involving human subjects: the principles of respect of persons, beneficence and justice.

What is beneficence principle?

The principle of beneficence is a moral obligation to act for the benefit of others.

What does the Belmont Report focus on?

Informed by monthly discussions that spanned nearly four years and an intensive four days of deliberation in 1976, the Commission published the Belmont Report, which identifies basic ethical principles and guidelines that address ethical issues arising from the conduct of research with human subjects.